Theory and (Lack of) Practice
Jure Vidmar
abstract
It is generally accepted in international legal scholarship that the right of self-determination is limited by the principle of territorial integrity of states. Yet the
inverted reading of the elaboration of this principle in the Declaration on Principles
of International Law suggests that a state may not avail itself of the principle of
territorial integrity if it does not possess a government representing the whole
people belonging to its territory.
Such an interpretation has some notable support
in judicial writings and even some limited support in jurisprudence. It is suggested
that secession may be the last resort for ending oppression. This doctrine is often
referred to as remedial secession. The article considers the theory and practice of
remedial secession and points out that its theoretical foundations are rather weak.
It concludes that secession is never an entitlement, not even in a situation of severe
oppression. Yet it may well be that international recognition is more likely to be
granted when oppressed peoples try to create their own state. Thus, although not
an entitlement, remedial secession may be given effect through recognition. In the
United Nations (un) Charter era, the secessions of Bangladesh and Kosovo and the
dissolutions of the Soviet Union and Yugoslavia are sometimes invoked as situations
upholding the remedial secession doctrine.
The article analyses these situations and
concludes that none of them proves that state practice accepts remedial secession as
a legal entitlement. Therefore, the remedial secession doctrine not only has weak
theoretical foundations, but also no support in state practice.
Introduction
The operation of the right of self-determination is not limited to the process of decolonization.1
Yet, the exercise of this right has different implications in colonial versus non-colonial situations. In the colonial context
“the only territorial relationship to be altered was that with the metropolitan power.
Achieving independence … did not come at the expense
of another sovereign state’s territory or that of an adjacent colony.”2
However, in non-colonial situations the right of self-determination collides
with the principle of territorial integrity. Since self-determination is not
an absolute right, the territorial integrity of states limits its scope of operation.
3
Therefore, outside of the process of decolonization, the exercise
Jure Vidmar, “Remedial Secession in International Law: Theory and (Lack
of) Practice,” St Antony’s International Review 6, no. 1 (2010): 37–56.
Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2060318
38 of the right of self-determination does not usually result in the creation
of a new state.
In non-colonial situations, secession can only take place with the approval of the parent state. Such approval may be given by the constitution
of the parent state, or in some other form, either prior to the declaration
of independence or following an initial unilateral declaration.
4 In either
event, due to the requirement of parent-state approval, there cannot be
said to be a right to secession as such under international law.5
Yet, the right of states to territorial integrity might not be absolute
and unqualified.
The development of international human rights law has
in many respects limited the concept of state sovereignty. In particular,
for our purposes here, the theory of so-called remedial secession suggests that gross and systematic human rights violations can lead a state
to lose a part of its territory if oppression is directed against a specific
people.
6
While the principle of territorial integrity limits the right of selfdetermination, it is precisely the elaboration of this principle in the
Declaration on Principles of International Law which gives rise to the
remedial secession theory:
Nothing in the foregoing paragraphs [concerning the right of self-determination]
shall be construed as authorizing or encouraging any action which would
dismember or impair, totally or in part, the territorial integrity or political unity
of sovereign and independent States conducting themselves in compliance with
the principle of equal rights and self-determination of peoples as described above
and thus possessed of a government representing the whole people belonging to
the territory without distinction as to race, creed or colour.
7
An inverted reading of this provision would suggest that a state which
does not possess “a government representing the whole people belonging to the territory without any distinction” is not entitled to invoke the
principle of territorial integrity when limiting the right of self-determination.
Still, it is questionable whether remedial secession has enough
support in legal doctrine and state practice to be considered an actual
entitlement under international law.
This article aims to clarify the theory and practice of remedial secession. It initially considers whether international law provides oppressed
peoples with the right to secession without approval of the parent state.
It then examines the practice of new state creation in a series of situations which are commonly cited as supportive of the remedial secession
doctrine: the secession of East Pakistan, the dissolution of the Soviet
Union, the dissolution of the Socialist Federal Republic of Yugoslavia
(sfry), and the secession of Kosovo.
The article is generally sceptical
about interpreting remedial secession as an entitlement, but nevertheless 39
shows that the concept has some relevance in international law.
The Theory of Remedial Secession
Perhaps the most prominent judicial pronouncement which underpins
the theory of remedial secession is that of the Supreme Court of Canada
in the Quebec case.
In its 1998 judgement, the Court affirmed that there
exists no right to unilateral secession in international law. However, this
statement was not unqualified:
The recognized sources of international law establish that the right to
self-determination of a people is normally fulfilled through internal selfdetermination—a people’s pursuit of its political, economic, social and cultural
development within a framework of an existing state.
A right to external selfdetermination (which in this case potentially takes the form of the assertion of a
right to unilateral secession) arises in only the most extreme of cases and, even
then, under carefully defined circumstances.8
Reference to “the most extreme cases,” which may justify a unilateral secession, is to be read against the background of the above-cited provision
on self-determination and territorial integrity expressed in the Declaration on Principles of International Law. This provision has been referred
to as the “safeguard clause.
” The Supreme Court of Canada seems to
have upheld the inverted reading of the safeguard clause by arguing:
“The other clear case where a right to external self-determination accrues [apart from colonial situations] is where a people is subject to alien
subjugation, domination or exploitation outside a colonial context.”9 The
Court, however, held that these circumstances were not met in the case
of Quebec,10 and the pronouncement remained an obiter dictum, i.e., a remark by the Court which was not necessary for reaching the decision.
In the 1997 case of Loizidou v Turkey, before the European Court of
Human Rights, Judges Wildhaber and Ryssdal argued:
In recent years a consensus has seemed to emerge that peoples may also exercise
a right to self-determination if their human rights are consistently and flagrantly
violated or if they are without representation at all or are massively underrepresented in an undemocratic and discriminatory way. If this description is
correct, then the right to self-determination is a tool which may be used to reestablish international standards of human rights and democracy.
11
The two concurring judges did not make a reference to secession. Yet
this omission is not too significant. The right of self-determination is
applicable to all peoples and there is no need for this to be specifically af-
40 firmed in a concurring opinion.12 Yet, the exercise of the right of self-determination in the form of secession is another question and the context
suggests that this is what Judges Wildhaber and Ryssdal had in mind.
Their concurring opinion obviously adopts the remedial secession argument and accepts the possibility of secession in situations where peoples
are oppressed by and/or not adequately represented within the political
structures of their parent states.
The support for remedial secession in jurisprudence is therefore limited to an obiter dictum and to a concurring opinion of two judges; no
judicial body has accepted secession as an entitlement in any particular
case.
The concept nevertheless has some support among writers.13 The
main argument of the academic proponents is well-captured by Allen
Buchanan:
If the state persists in serious injustices toward a group, and the group’s forming
its own independent political unit is a remedy of last resort for these injustices,
then the group ought to be acknowledged by the international community to
have the claim-right to repudiate the authority of the state and to attempt to
establish its own independent political unit.
14
The academic proponents of remedial secession thus tend to see secession as a “qualified right” which is triggered by oppression.15 At the same
time, it is viewed as an exceptional, last-resort solution.16
However, as James Summers points out, most writers express their
support for remedial secession rather cautiously by claiming that such a
right “perhaps” or “possibly” exists, or by giving a circular reference to
“a number of commentators,” without taking a firm stance on whether
this right exists or not.
17 Malcolm Shaw further argues that a theory
based on an inverted reading of the safeguard clause is problematic:
Such a major change in legal principle cannot be introduced by way of an
ambiguous subordinate clause, especially when the principle of territorial integrity
has always been accepted and proclaimed as a core principle of international law,
and is indeed placed before the qualifying clause in the provision in question.
18
The relevant judicial decisions and academic writings do not, therefore,
provide sufficient evidence to suggest that in international legal doctrine,
remedial secession is a universally-accepted entitlement of oppressed
peoples. But, as will be discussed next, the idea underlying remedial
secession—the last resort for ending the oppression of a certain people—
can still influence the recognition policies of states.
The Effects of Remedial Secession through Recognition
41
The absence of a right to unilateral secession does not imply that such
an act is illegal. Indeed, “secession is neither legal nor illegal in international law, but a legally neutral act the consequences of which are regulated internationally.
”19 In the era of the un Charter, it is very unlikely
that an attempt at unilateral secession would result in the creation of a
new state, but such an outcome is not excluded. In the Quebec case, the
Supreme Court of Canada held that:
The ultimate success of … a [unilateral] secession would be dependent on
recognition by the international community, which is likely to consider the
legality and legitimacy of secession having regard to, amongst other facts, the
conduct of Quebec and Canada, in determining whether to grant or withhold
recognition.
20
This position of the Court suggests that (1) the success of a unilateral
secession depends on international recognition; and (2) the conduct of
the parent state toward the independence-seeking entity will be taken as
a major consideration when states decide on granting recognition.
The
judgement therefore implies that remedial secession could be given effect
through recognition—indeed, it falls close to Shaw’s argument that “recognition may be more forthcoming where the secession has occurred as
a consequence of violations of human rights.
”21
Any argument suggesting that recognition could create states needs
to be taken with caution, as it could be problematic in light of the general perception in contemporary international law that recognition is a
declaratory and not a constitutive act. This is indeed true in situations
where the emergence of a new state is not disputable—when statehood
criteria are met and there is no claim to territorial integrity by a parent
state. Yet, in cases concerning the recognition of an entity with ambiguous legal status, recognition itself can “have the effect of providing crucial evidence of an entity’s status.
”22 Furthermore, where recognition is
granted almost universally to such an entity, it is difficult to separate
collective recognition from collective state creation.23 For these reasons
it is possible to accept that remedial-secession claims could be realized
through recognition.
But there is an important limitation on giving effect to remedial
secession via recognition. While, in a situation of oppression, states
might be able to grant recognition to a secession-seeking entity without offending the territorial integrity of its parent state,24 there are no
circumstances that create an international legal obligation to grant such
42 recognition.
25 The actual position of remedial secession in international
law may therefore be as follows: that, as a consequence of oppression,
the parent state’s right to territorial integrity becomes weaker; foreign
states might then decide not to observe this right of the parent state and
to recognize the secession-seeking entity; however, remedial secession
is not an entitlement of oppressed peoples and oppression creates no
obligation for foreign states to grant recognition. It now needs to be considered whether remedial secession has been given any prominence in
state practice.
Conclusion
Remedial secession, interpreted as the last resort of subjugated peoples
for ending oppression, has received some support among writers. However, the foundations of the doctrine remain controversial both in theory
and in practice.
Theoretically, it is questionable whether remedial secession can be founded on the inverted reading of the provision on territorial integrity within the Declaration on Principles of International Law.
It would appear that “[s]uch a major change in legal principle [concerning the territorial integrity of states] cannot be introduced by way of an
ambiguous subordinate clause.
”96 The doctrine has been given some attention in judicial decisions. Yet, no international judicial body has ever
upheld the remedial secession argument in relation to a specific attempt
at unilateral secession.
Remedial secession was, at best, mentioned as an
obiter dictum and, even then, not unequivocally as an entitlement.
The idea of remedial secession nevertheless has some merit, not least
if it can be given effect through international recognition. Although recognition in contemporary international law is deemed to be a declaratory act, universal collective recognition can have the effect of collective
state creation.
It may be that, where oppressed peoples seek secession,
the international community will be more willing to ignore the territo-
rial integrity of the parent state and grant recognition to the secession- 51
seeking entity.
Although the explanation that remedial secession could be given effect through the act of recognition may be able to clarify the theoretical status of remedial secession in international law, there is a marked
absence of state practice. This article shows that no single instance of
non-colonial new state creation in the un Charter era serves as a clear
example of remedial secession. The international community of states
has never accepted either the right of oppressed peoples to secession or
the duty to grant recognition when oppressed peoples are trying to create their own state.
https://www.blogger.com/blogger.g?blogID=4970037790068451325#editor/target=post;postID=1035543691351185444
Tuesday, July 7, 2020
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment